Results for 'George S. Botterill'

1000+ found
Order:
See also
George Steven Botterill
University of Sheffield
  1. Contrast, inference and scientific realism.Mark Day & George S. Botterill - 2008 - Synthese 160 (2):249-267.
    The thesis of underdetermination presents a major obstacle to the epistemological claims of scientific realism. That thesis is regularly assumed in the philosophy of science, but is puzzlingly at odds with the actual history of science, in which empirically adequate theories are thin on the ground. We propose to advance a case for scientific realism which concentrates on the process of scientific reasoning rather than its theoretical products. Developing an account of causal–explanatory inference will make it easier to resist the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  2. Beliefs, functionally discrete states, and connectionist networks.George Botterill - 1994 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 45 (3):899-906.
  3.  62
    Falsification and the existence of God: A discussion of Plantinga's free will defence.George Botterill - 1977 - Philosophical Quarterly 27 (107):114-134.
  4.  2
    Hume's System: An examination of the First Book of His.George Botterill - 1992 - Philosophical Books 33 (1):11-13.
  5.  57
    Learning from Error: Karl Popper's Psychology of Learning.George Botterill - 1986 - Philosophical Books 27 (2):98-100.
  6.  50
    Right and Wrong Reasons in Folk‐Psychological Explanation.George Botterill - 2009 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 17 (4):463 – 488.
    Davidson argued that the fact we can have a reason for acting, and yet not be the reason why we act, requires explanation of action in terms of the agent's reasons to be causal. The present paper agrees with Dickenson (_Pacific Philosophical Quarterly_, 2007) in taking this argument to be an inference to the best explanation. However, its target phenomenon is the very existence of a case in which an agent has more than one reason, but acts exclusively becaue of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7.  71
    The internal problem of dreaming: Detection and epistemic risk.George Botterill - 2008 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 16 (2):139 – 160.
    There are two epistemological problems connected with dreaming, which are of different kinds and require different treatment. The internal problem is best seen as a problem of rational consistency, of how we can maintain all of: Dreams are experiences we have during sleep. Dream-experiences are sufficiently similar to waking experiences for the subject to be able to mistake them for waking experiences. We can tell that we are awake. (1)-(3) threaten to violate a requirement on discrimination: that we can only (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8. Contrastive explanation and the many absences problem.Jane Suilin Lavelle, George Botterill & Suzanne Lock - 2013 - Synthese 190 (16):3495-3510.
    We often explain by citing an absence or an omission. Apart from the problem of assigning a causal role to such apparently negative factors as absences and omissions, there is a puzzle as to why only some absences and omissions, out of indefinitely many, should figure in explanations. In this paper we solve this ’many absences problem’ by using the contrastive model of explanation. The contrastive model of explanation is developed by adapting Peter Lipton’s account. What initially appears to be (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  9.  15
    Why beliefs are not dispositional stereotypes.Andrew Garford Moore & George Botterill - 2023 - Theoria 89 (4):483-494.
    In a series of papers, Schwitzgebel has attempted to revive the dispositionalist account of belief by tweaking it a little and claiming a previously unconsidered advantage over representationalism. The tweaks are to include phenomenal and cognitive responses, in addition to overt behaviour, in the manifestations of a given belief; and to soften the account of dispositions by allowing for dispositional stereotypes. The alleged advantage is that dispositionalism can deal with what Schwitzgebel calls cases of in‐between belief, whereas representationalism cannot. In (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  10.  23
    Particles and Ideas: Bishop Berkeley's Corpuscularian Philosophy. [REVIEW]George Botterill - 1990 - Philosophical Books 31 (2):75-77.
  11.  35
    Computability and Logic.George S. Boolos, John P. Burgess & Richard C. Jeffrey - 1974 - Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press. Edited by John P. Burgess & Richard C. Jeffrey.
  12. Computability and Logic.George S. Boolos, John P. Burgess & Richard C. Jeffrey - 2003 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 9 (4):520-521.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   150 citations  
  13.  24
    Logic, Logic, and Logic.George S. Boolos & Richard C. Jeffrey - 1998 - Cambridge, MA, USA: Harvard University Press. Edited by Richard C. Jeffrey.
    George Boolos was one of the most prominent and influential logician-philosophers of recent times. This collection, nearly all chosen by Boolos himself shortly before his death, includes thirty papers on set theory, second-order logic, and plural quantifiers; on Frege, Dedekind, Cantor, and Russell; and on miscellaneous topics in logic and proof theory, including three papers on various aspects of the Gödel theorems. Boolos is universally recognized as the leader in the renewed interest in studies of Frege's work on logic (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  14. On second-order logic.George S. Boolos - 1975 - Journal of Philosophy 72 (16):509-527.
  15.  26
    An Attractor Model of Lexical Conceptual Processing: Simulating Semantic Priming.George S. Cree, Ken McRae & Chris McNorgan - 1999 - Cognitive Science 23 (3):371-414.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  16.  37
    Analyzing the factors underlying the structure and computation of the meaning of< em> chipmunk,< em> cherry,< em> chisel,< em> cheese, and< em> cello(and many other such concrete nouns).George S. Cree & Ken McRae - 2003 - Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 132 (2):163.
  17. Dare the school build a new social order?George S. Counts - 2008 - In David J. Flinders & Stephen J. Thornton (eds.), The Curriculum Studies Reader. Routledge.
    George S. Counts was a_ _major figure in American education for almost fifty years. Republication of this early work draws special attention to Counts’s role as a social and political activist. Three particular themes make the book noteworthy because of their importance in Counts’s plan for change as well as for their continuing contem­porary importance: _ _Counts’s crit­icism of child-centered progressives; _ _the role Counts assigns to teachers in achieving educational and social re­form; and Counts’s idea for the re­form (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  18. Aristotle's Criticism of Plato's « Timaeus ».George S. Claghorn - 1965 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 155:514-517.
  19.  47
    Animals, Heidegger, and the Right to Life.George S. Cave - 1982 - Environmental Ethics 4 (3):249-254.
    Quantitative utilitarianism demands equal treatment of human and nonhuman animals where there are no relevant differences between them. A difference is relevant only if it excludes the animal from suffering evil if it is treated differently. Quantitative utilitarianism cannot, however, resolve conflicts of interest nor prove that painless killing of animals is morally wrong. For this we need a higher qualitativegood. I suggest Care, as Heidegger understands it, is such a good, and that it is the essence not only of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  20. Aristotle's Criticism of Plato's "Timaeus".George S. Claghorn - 1957 - Philosophy 32 (120):84-85.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  21.  13
    The richest man in Babylon: the complete original edition, with bonus essay "Acres of diamonds".George S. Clason - 1926 - New York: St. Martin's Essentials. Edited by Russell H. Conwell.
    The Most Important Book on Money You'll Ever Read Also Includes Acres of Diamond The Richest Man in Babylon is a transformative book that has changed the way millions of people think about money since it was first published in 1926. Through light, entertaining parables author George S. Clason shares profound truths about wealth and success that will revolutionize the way you relate to money and interact with your finances. Clason's wisdom has inspired countless readers to gain, grow, and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  8
    The richest man in Babylon: the success secrets of the ancients.George S. Clason - 2022 - Garden City, New York: Ixia Press.
    "Money is plentiful for those who understand the simple laws which govern its acquisition." Read by millions, The Richest Man in Babylon is a classic that offers today's readers a path to success, prosperity, and happiness. Originally published in 1926 as a series of inspirational pamphlets for financial institutions, Clason's work offers financial advice for creating personal wealth using parables set in ancient Babylon. The stories, based on a fictional character, Arkad, are easy to read and packed with priceless wisdom. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. The Richest Man in Babylon.George S. Clason - 1926 - In The richest man in Babylon: the complete original edition, with bonus book Acres of diamonds. New York, NY: St. Martin's Essentials.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24. The Prospects of American Democracy.George S. Counts & Max Lerner - 1940 - Ethics 50 (2):227-229.
  25.  6
    On Kalmar's consistency proof and a generalization of the notion of ω-consistency.George S. Boolos - 1975 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 17 (1-2):3-7.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  18
    Beyond the sensory/functional dichotomy.George S. Cree & Ken McRae - 2001 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 24 (3):480-481.
    Most current theories of category-specific semantic deficits appeal to the role of sensory and functional knowledge types in explaining patients' impairments. We discuss why this binary classification is inadequate, point to a more detailed knowledge type taxonomy, and suggest how it may provide insight into the relationships between category-specific semantic deficits and impairments of specific aspects of knowledge.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. Internalist vs. Externalist Conceptions of Epistemic Justification.George S. Pappas - forthcoming - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  28. Essays on Knowledge and Justification.George S. Pappas & Marshall Swain - 1978 - Critica 10 (29):140-143.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  29.  59
    Symposiums papers: Sensation and perception in Reid.George S. Pappas - 1989 - Noûs 23 (2):155-167.
  30. Essays on Knowledge and Justification.George S. Pappas & Marshall Swain - 1979 - Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 33 (4):647-650.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  31.  36
    Arithmetical Functions and Minimalization.George S. Boolos - 1974 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 20 (23-24):353-354.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  57
    Some conclusive reasons against 'conclusive reasons'.George S. Pappas & Marshall Swain - 1973 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 51 (1):72 – 76.
  33.  66
    Ideas, Minds, and Berkeley.George S. Pappas - 1980 - American Philosophical Quarterly 17 (3):181 - 194.
    A number of commentators on the work of berkeley have maintained that berkeleyan minds are related to ideas by the relation of inherence. Thus, Ideas are taken to inhere in minds in something like the way that accidents were supposed to inhere in substances for the aristotelian. This inherence account, As I call it, Is spelled out in detail and critically evaluated. Ultimately it is rejected despite its considerable initial plausibility.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  34.  31
    Minds, Machines and Gödel.George S. Boolos - 1968 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 33 (4):613-615.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  35.  16
    The Longing for Myth in Germany: Religion and Aesthetic Culture From Romanticism to Nietzsche.George S. Williamson - 2004 - University of Chicago Press.
    Since the dawn of Romanticism, artists and intellectuals in Germany have maintained an abiding interest in the gods and myths of antiquity while calling for a new mythology suitable to the modern age. In this study, George S. Williamson examines the factors that gave rise to this distinct and profound longing for myth. In doing so, he demonstrates the entanglement of aesthetic and philosophical ambitions in Germany with some of the major religious conflicts of the nineteenth century. Through readings (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  36.  93
    Abstract General Ideas in Hume.George S. Pappas - 1989 - Hume Studies 15 (2):339-352.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Abstract General Ideas in Hume George S. Pappas Hume followed Berkeley in rejecting abstract general ideas; that is, both of these philosophers rejected the view that one could engage in the operation or activity ofabstraction — a kind ofmental separation ofentities that are inseparable in reality —as well as the view that the alleged products of such an activity — ideas which are intrinsically general — really exist. (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  37.  62
    Hume and Abstract General Ideas.George S. Pappas - 1977 - Hume Studies 3 (1):17-31.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:17. HUME AND ABSTRACT GENERAL IDEAS In his discussion of abstract ideas in the Treatise, Hume offers what "...may... be thought... a plain dilemma, that decides concerning the nature of those abstract ideas..." He states the dilemma in these words: The abstract idea of a man represents men of all sizes and all qualities; which 'tis concluded it cannot do, but either by representing at once all possible sizes (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  38. Causation and perception in Reid.George S. Pappas - 1990 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 50 (4):763-766.
  39. Modern European Philosophy.George S. Tomlinson - 2019 - The Year's Work in Critical and Cultural Theory 27 (1):220–241.
    This chapter reviews four books published in 2018 which are not readily categorized as works in ‘modern European philosophy’: Gurminder K. Bhambra, Kerem Nişancloğlu, and Dalia Gebrial’s edited volume Decolonising the University, Chantal Mouffe’s For a Left Populism, Cinzia Arruzza, Tithi Bhattacharya, and Nancy Fraser’s Feminism for the 99%, and Andreas Malm’s The Progress of this Storm. Yet their uneasy relationship to this philosophy is precisely the reason they constitute a significant contribution to it. The philosophical originality and critical purchase (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. Totalization, Temporalization, and History: Marx and Sartre.George S. Tomlinson - 2014 - In Lisa Jeschke and Adrian May (ed.), Matters of Time: Material Temporalities in Twentieth-Century French Culture. Oxford, Bern, Berlin, Bruxelles, Frankfurt am Main, New York, Wien: pp. 87-102.
    This chapter picks up on what Heidegger in his 1949 ‘Letter on ‘Humanism’’ calls ‘the historical in being’, that dimension of being within which, for Heidegger, a ‘productive dialogue’ between phenomenology and existentialism, on the one hand, and Marxism, on the other, ‘first becomes possible.’ It introduces the possibility of this dialogue through a particular, and particularly revealing, problem with The German Ideology: namely, Marx and Engels offer no analysis of the relationship between time, temporality and their materialist concept of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  16
    Voices calling for reform: The Royal Society in the mid-eighteenth century: Martin Folkes, John Hill, and William Stukeley.George S. Rousseau & David Haycock - 1999 - History of Science 37 (118):377-406.
  42. Seeinge and seeingn.George S. Pappas - 1976 - Mind 85 (338):171-188.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  43.  56
    On some philosophical accounts of perception.George S. Pappas - 2003 - Journal of Philosophical Research 28 (Supplement):71-82.
    Philosophical accounts of perception in the tradition of Kant and Reid have generally supposed that an event of making a judgment is a key element in every perceptual experience. An alternative very austere view regards perception as an event containing nothing judgmental, nor anything conceptual. This account of perception as nonconceptual is discussed first historically as found in the philosophies of Locke and (briefly) Berkeley, and then examined in the contemporary work of Chisholm and Alston.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  44.  46
    When psychology looks like a "soft" science, it's for good reasonp.George S. Howard - 1993 - Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology 13 (1):42-47.
    The natural sciences are sometimes called "hard" sciences in contrast to the social sciences , which are thought to represent "soft" sciences. L. V. Hedges made an important effort to determine the empirical cumulativeness of various scientific research programs, with an eye toward assessing if this criterion is related to a discipline's "hardness" or "softness." This article discusses another criterion, a research program's predictive accuracy, that might also be considered along with a program's empirical cumulativeness. Finally, recent improvements in the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. Berkeley's Assessment of Locke's Epistemology.George S. Pappas - 2007 - In Stephen H. Daniel (ed.), Philosophica.
    In this essay, the author analyses Berkeley’s conformity and inference argument against Locke’s theory of percep tion. Both arguments are not as decisive as traditionally has been perceived and fail to engage in Locke’s actual position. The main reason for this is that Berkeley does not see that Locke’s position is compatible with the non-inferential nature of perceptual knowledge.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  18
    Berkeley’s assessment of Locke’s epistemology.George S. Pappas - 2005 - Philosophica 76 (2).
    In this essay, the author analyses Berkeley’s conformity and inference argument against Locke’s theory of percep tion. Both arguments are not as decisive as traditionally has been perceived and fail to engage in Locke’s actual position. The main reason for this is that Berkeley does not see that Locke’s position is compatible with the non-inferential nature of perceptual knowledge.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  36
    Armstrong's materialism.George S. Pappas - 1977 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 7 (September):569-592.
    Central-state materialism is a very strong, but also very exciting theory of mind according to which each mental state is identical with a state of the central nervous system. CSM thus goes considerably beyond early versions of the identity theory of mind, since those early accounts held only that sensations are to be identified with neural events. CSM, by contrast, is a thesis about all mental states; every mental state is held to be a state of the central nervous system. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  53
    Berkeley's Positive Epistemology.George S. Pappas - 2011 - Philosophical Inquiry 35 (3-4):23-35.
  49.  9
    The effects of sodium amobarbital on odor-based responding in rats.George S. Howard & James H. Mchose - 1974 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 3 (3):185-186.
  50.  33
    On McRae's Hume.George S. Pappas - 1981 - Hume Studies 7 (2):167-171.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:167. ON McRAE' S HUME Professor McRae's interesting paper may be rather naturally divided into two parts. In the first part he explains what he takes Hume's account of time to be; in the second he advances the bold thesis that Hume's account of time, or perhaps of duration, provides a basis or foundation for his more widely discussed remarks on identity, substance, the self, the necessary connections. In (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 1000